mirror of
https://git.savannah.gnu.org/git/emacs.git
synced 2024-12-27 10:54:40 +00:00
245 lines
11 KiB
Plaintext
245 lines
11 KiB
Plaintext
Why Software Should Not Have Owners
|
|
|
|
by Richard Stallman
|
|
|
|
Digital information technology contributes to the world by making it
|
|
easier to copy and modify information. Computers promise to make this
|
|
easier for all of us.
|
|
|
|
Not everyone wants it to be easier. The system of copyright gives
|
|
software programs "owners", most of whom aim to withhold software's
|
|
potential benefit from the rest of the public. They would like to be
|
|
the only ones who can copy and modify the software that we use.
|
|
|
|
The copyright system grew up with printing--a technology for mass
|
|
production copying. Copyright fit in well with this technology
|
|
because it restricted only the mass producers of copies. It did not
|
|
take freedom away from readers of books. An ordinary reader, who did
|
|
not own a printing press, could copy books only with pen and ink, and
|
|
few readers were sued for that.
|
|
|
|
Digital technology is more flexible than the printing press: when
|
|
information has digital form, you can easily copy it to share it with
|
|
others. This very flexibility makes a bad fit with a system like
|
|
copyright. That's the reason for the increasingly nasty and draconian
|
|
measures now used to enforce software copyright. Consider these four
|
|
practices of the Software Publishers Association (SPA):
|
|
|
|
* Massive propaganda saying it is wrong to disobey the owners
|
|
to help your friend.
|
|
|
|
* Solicitation for stool pigeons to inform on their coworkers and
|
|
colleagues.
|
|
|
|
* Raids (with police help) on offices and schools, in which people are
|
|
told they must prove they are innocent of illegal copying.
|
|
|
|
* Prosecution (by the US government, at the SPA's request) of people
|
|
such as MIT's David LaMacchia, not for copying software (he is not
|
|
accused of copying any), but merely for leaving copying facilities
|
|
unguarded and failing to censor their use.
|
|
|
|
All four practices resemble those used in the former Soviet Union,
|
|
where every copying machine had a guard to prevent forbidden copying,
|
|
and where individuals had to copy information secretly and pass it
|
|
from hand to hand as "samizdat". There is of course a difference: the
|
|
motive for information control in the Soviet Union was political; in
|
|
the US the motive is profit. But it is the actions that affect us,
|
|
not the motive. Any attempt to block the sharing of information, no
|
|
matter why, leads to the same methods and the same harshness.
|
|
|
|
Owners make several kinds of arguments for giving them the power
|
|
to control how we use information:
|
|
|
|
* Name calling.
|
|
|
|
Owners use smear words such as "piracy" and "theft", as well as expert
|
|
terminology such as "intellectual property" and "damage", to suggest a
|
|
certain line of thinking to the public--a simplistic analogy between
|
|
programs and physical objects.
|
|
|
|
Our ideas and intuitions about property for material objects are about
|
|
whether it is right to *take an object away* from someone else. They
|
|
don't directly apply to *making a copy* of something. But the owners
|
|
ask us to apply them anyway.
|
|
|
|
* Exaggeration.
|
|
|
|
Owners say that they suffer "harm" or "economic loss" when users copy
|
|
programs themselves. But the copying has no direct effect on the
|
|
owner, and it harms no one. The owner can lose only if the person who
|
|
made the copy would otherwise have paid for one from the owner.
|
|
|
|
A little thought shows that most such people would not have bought
|
|
copies. Yet the owners compute their "losses" as if each and every
|
|
one would have bought a copy. That is exaggeration--to put it kindly.
|
|
|
|
* The law.
|
|
|
|
Owners often describe the current state of the law, and the harsh
|
|
penalties they can threaten us with. Implicit in this approach is the
|
|
suggestion that today's law reflects an unquestionable view of
|
|
morality--yet at the same time, we are urged to regard these penalties
|
|
as facts of nature that can't be blamed on anyone.
|
|
|
|
This line of persuasion isn't designed to stand up to critical
|
|
thinking; it's intended to reinforce a habitual mental pathway.
|
|
|
|
It's elemental that laws don't decide right and wrong. Every American
|
|
should know that, forty years ago, it was against the law in many
|
|
states for a black person to sit in the front of a bus; but only
|
|
racists would say sitting there was wrong.
|
|
|
|
* Natural rights.
|
|
|
|
Authors often claim a special connection with programs they have
|
|
written, and go on to assert that, as a result, their desires and
|
|
interests concerning the program simply outweigh those of anyone
|
|
else--or even those of the whole rest of the world. (Typically
|
|
companies, not authors, hold the copyrights on software, but we are
|
|
expected to ignore this discrepancy.)
|
|
|
|
To those who propose this as an ethical axiom--the author is more
|
|
important than you--I can only say that I, a notable software author
|
|
myself, call it bunk.
|
|
|
|
But people in general are only likely to feel any sympathy with the
|
|
natural rights claims for two reasons.
|
|
|
|
One reason is an overstretched analogy with material objects. When I
|
|
cook spaghetti, I do object if someone else takes it and stops me from
|
|
eating it. In this case, that person and I have the same material
|
|
interests at stake, and it's a zero-sum game. The smallest
|
|
distinction between us is enough to tip the ethical balance.
|
|
|
|
But whether you run or change a program I wrote affects you directly
|
|
and me only indirectly. Whether you give a copy to your friend
|
|
affects you and your friend much more than it affects me. I shouldn't
|
|
have the power to tell you not to do these things. No one should.
|
|
|
|
The second reason is that people have been told that natural rights
|
|
for authors is the accepted and unquestioned tradition of our society.
|
|
|
|
As a matter of history, the opposite is true. The idea of natural
|
|
rights of authors was proposed and decisively rejected when the US
|
|
Constitution was drawn up. That's why the Constitution only *permits*
|
|
a system of copyright and does not *require* one; that's why it says
|
|
that copyright must be temporary. It also states that the purpose of
|
|
copyright is to promote progress--not to reward authors. Copyright
|
|
does reward authors somewhat, and publishers more, but that is
|
|
intended as a means of modifying their behavior.
|
|
|
|
The real established tradition of our society is that copyright cuts
|
|
into the natural rights of the public--and that this can only be
|
|
justified for the public's sake.
|
|
|
|
* Economics.
|
|
|
|
The final argument made for having owners of software is that this
|
|
leads to production of more software.
|
|
|
|
Unlike the others, this argument at least takes a legitimate approach
|
|
to the subject. It is based on a valid goal--satisfying the users of
|
|
software. And it is empirically clear that people will produce more of
|
|
something if they are well paid for doing so.
|
|
|
|
But the economic argument has a flaw: it is based on the assumption
|
|
that the difference is only a matter of how much money we have to pay.
|
|
It assumes that "production of software" is what we want, whether the
|
|
software has owners or not.
|
|
|
|
People readily accept this assumption because it accords with our
|
|
experiences with material objects. Consider a sandwich, for instance.
|
|
You might well be able to get an equivalent sandwich either free or
|
|
for a price. If so, the amount you pay is the only difference.
|
|
Whether or not you have to buy it, the sandwich has the same taste,
|
|
the same nutritional value, and in either case you can only eat it
|
|
once. Whether you get the sandwich from an owner or not cannot
|
|
directly affect anything but the amount of money you have afterwards.
|
|
|
|
This is true for any kind of material object--whether or not it has an
|
|
owner does not directly affect what it *is*, or what you can do with
|
|
it if you acquire it.
|
|
|
|
But if a program has an owner, this very much affects what it is, and
|
|
what you can do with a copy if you buy one. The difference is not
|
|
just a matter of money. The system of owners of software encourages
|
|
software owners to produce something--but not what society really
|
|
needs. And it causes intangible ethical pollution that affects us
|
|
all.
|
|
|
|
What does society need? It needs information that is truly available
|
|
to its citizens--for example, programs that people can read, fix,
|
|
adapt, and improve, not just operate. But what software owners
|
|
typically deliver is a black box that we can't study or change.
|
|
|
|
Society also needs freedom. When a program has an owner, the users
|
|
lose freedom to control part of their own lives.
|
|
|
|
And above all society needs to encourage the spirit of voluntary
|
|
cooperation in its citizens. When software owners tell us that
|
|
helping our neighbors in a natural way is "piracy", they pollute our
|
|
society's civic spirit.
|
|
|
|
This is why we say that free software is a matter of freedom, not
|
|
price.
|
|
|
|
The economic argument for owners is erroneous, but the economic issue
|
|
is real. Some people write useful software for the pleasure of
|
|
writing it or for admiration and love; but if we want more software
|
|
than those people write, we need to raise funds.
|
|
|
|
For ten years now, free software developers have tried various methods
|
|
of finding funds, with some success. There's no need to make anyone
|
|
rich; the median US family income, around $35k, proves to be enough
|
|
incentive for many jobs that are less satisfying than programming.
|
|
|
|
For years, until a fellowship made it unnecessary, I made a living
|
|
from custom enhancements of the free software I had written. Each
|
|
enhancement was added to the standard released version and thus
|
|
eventually became available to the general public. Clients paid me so
|
|
that I would work on the enhancements they wanted, rather than on the
|
|
features I would otherwise have considered highest priority.
|
|
|
|
The Free Software Foundation, a tax-exempt charity for free software
|
|
development, raises funds by selling CD-ROMs, tapes and manuals (all
|
|
of which users are free to copy and change), as well as from
|
|
donations. It now has a staff of five programmers, plus three
|
|
employees who handle mail orders.
|
|
|
|
Some free software developers make money by selling support services.
|
|
Cygnus Support, with around 50 employees, estimates that about 15 per
|
|
cent of its staff activity is free software development--a respectable
|
|
percentage for a software company.
|
|
|
|
Companies including Intel, Motorola, Texas Instruments and Analog
|
|
Devices have combined to fund the continued development of the free
|
|
GNU compiler for the language C. Meanwhile, the GNU compiler for the
|
|
Ada language is being funded by the US Air Force, which believes this
|
|
is the most cost-effective way to get a high quality compiler.
|
|
|
|
All these examples are small; the free software movement is still
|
|
small, and still young. But the example of listener-supported radio
|
|
in this country shows it's possible to support a large activity
|
|
without forcing each user to pay.
|
|
|
|
As a computer user today, you may find yourself using a proprietary
|
|
program. If your friend asks to make a copy, it would be wrong to
|
|
refuse. Cooperation is more important than copyright. But
|
|
underground, closet cooperation does not make for a good society. A
|
|
person should aspire to live an upright life openly with pride, and
|
|
this means saying "No" to proprietary software.
|
|
|
|
You deserve to be able to cooperate openly and freely with other
|
|
people who use software. You deserve to be able to learn how the
|
|
software works, and to teach your students with it. You deserve to be
|
|
able to hire your favorite programmer to fix it when it breaks.
|
|
|
|
You deserve free software.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Copyright 1994 Richard Stallman
|
|
Verbatim copying and redistribution is permitted
|
|
without royalty as long as this notice is preserved;
|
|
alteration is not permitted.
|